ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER’S MIRROR: THE WILL, THE SUFFERING, THE COMPASSION AS PHILOSOPHICAL CHALLENGES

Authors

  • Ana BAZAC Professor, Division of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science; Romanian Committee for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology, Romanian Academy, Bucharest, Romania. Email: ana_bazac@hotmail.com.

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.24193/subbphil.2019.3.09

Keywords:

Schopenhauer, Kant, German idealism, constructivism, will, living force, suffering, compassion, philosophical reception, the present

Abstract

Arthur Schopenhauer’s Mirror: the Will, the Suffering, the Compassion as Philosophical Challenges. In philosophy, the celebration of Arthur Schopenhauer has already ended. Only the last year was anniversary (of his birth and of the publication of the first volume of The World as Will and Representation), but the importance of this non-conformist creator is never superfluous to highlight. In this article, there is, certainly, a very limited/selective focus on the thinking of Schopenhauer, and no biographical approach: the goal is only to stress two aspects of his philosophy in their logic. Schopenhauer was an enthusiastic Kantian: first of all, by taking over his maestro’s seminal paradigm, the constructivism (that does not pertain only to the theory of knowledge, but marks the entire existence analysed at different philosophical levels). Secondly, by the ethical focus and accent, continuing Kant’s exceptional emphasis of the ultimate reason of the tableau of the world, the human reason and its power to treat the others in a moral manner. And certainly, Schopenhauer was not an epigone, but a creator, using and at the same time giving other content to the Kantian form of ethical revolution. Schopenhauer had, obviously, contradictory ideas – as that between his constructivism and his metaphysical treatment of the will, i. e. as the only principle explaining the world – and also with disputable significance, including for the actual life and thinking. But he had a bad publicity from the dominant philosophy – namely, some of his ideas (as that of the moral of compassion) were, and still are, absolutely ignored, while other ones were simplified or transformed in the conception of Schopenhauer, reducing this one to some ideas out of context – and even nowadays this tradition is dominant. And it’s pity, because Schopenhauer’s philosophy was and represented a dramatic moment in the history of the 19th century thinking and culture: as it is a strange mirror for the present much graver situation. In order to critique the present it’s not necessary to do it from Schopenhauer’s perspective. However, just his contradictory ideas and pathetic accent on compassion show better than ever that neither philosophy – as theoretical position – nor the urging for moral activism are more than vox clamantis in deserto: if the historical facts, which include this urging and the spring of thinking but are not confined to them, are missing.

References

Banham, Gary. “Kant and Leibniz on Living Force”, Kant Studien online, 2006, pp. 1-17.

Banham, Gary. “Kantian Cosmology: The Very Idea”, Kant Studien online, 2011, pp. 1-26.

Beiser, Frederic C. Late German Idealism: Trendelenburg and Lotze, Oxford University Press, 2016.

Besterman, T. (ed.), Les lettres de la Marquise de Châtelet, Genève, 1958.

Boury, Dominique. “Irritability and Sensibility: Key Concepts in Assessing the Medical Doctrines of Haller and Bordeu”, Science in Context, Vol. 21, Issue 4, December 2008, pp. 521-535.

Buess, Heinrich. “William Harwey and the Foundation of Modern haemodynamics by Albrecht von Haller”, Medical History, 1970 Apr; 14(2), pp. 175–182.

Decety, J. “The neuroevolution of empathy”, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 2011 Aug; 1231:35-45. doi: 10.1111/j.1749-6632.2011.06027.x. Epub 2011 Jun 8.

Decety, Jean, Margarita Svetlova, Putting together phylogenetic and ontogenetic perspectives on empathy, Developmental Cognitive Neuroscience, 2, 2012, pp. 1-24.

Depew, David. Empathy, Psychology, and Aesthetics: Reflections on a Repair Concept, Poroi, An Interdisciplinary Journal of Rhetorical Analysis and Invention, Vo. 4, issue 1, 2005, pp. 99-107.

de Waal, Frans B.M., Pier Francesco Ferrari. “Towards a bottom-up perspective on animal and human cognition”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol. 14. Issue 5, May 2010, pp. 201–207.

Gonzalez-Liencres, C., S.G. Shamay-Tsoory, M. Brüne, “Towards a neuroscience of empathy: ontogeny, phylogeny, brain mechanisms, context and psychopathology”, Neuroscience Biobehavioral Reviews, 2013 Sep; 37(8): 1537-48. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2013.05.001. Epub 2013 May 13.

Hegel, G.W.F. System of Ethical Life (1802), 1. Absolute Ethical Life on the Basis of Reason, a) The Subsumption of the Concept under Intuition, http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/hegel/works/se/ch01.htm.

Helmuth, L. “Cognitive neuroscience. Moral reasoning relies on emotion”, Science, 2001, Sep. 14, 293 (5537), pp. 1971-1972.

Iacoboni, Marco, Istvan Molnár-Szakács, Vittorio Gallese et al. “Grasping the intentions of others with one’s own mirror neuron system”, PLoS Biology 3(3), 2005, pp. 529 – 535.

Iltis, Carolyn. “Leibniz and the Vis Viva Controversy”, Isis, Vol. 62, No. 1, Spring 1971, pp. 21-35.

Iltis, Carolyn. “The Leibnizian-Newtonian Debates: Natural Philosophy and Social Psychology”, The British Journal for the History of Science, Vol. 6, No. 4, December 1973, pp. 343-377.

Jankowski, K. F., H. Takahashi, “Cognitive neuroscience of social emotions and implications for psychopathology: examining embarrassment, guilt, envy, and schadenfreude”, Psychiatry. Clinical Neuroscience, 2014 May; 68(5):319-36. doi: 10.1111/pcn.12182.

Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787), Translated by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood, Cambridge University Press, 1998.

Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Practical Reason (1788), Translated by Werner S. Pluhar, Introduction by Stephen Engstrom, Indianapolis/Cambridge, Hackett Publishing Company, 2002.

Leibniz, G.W. “On the Reform of Metaphysics and of the Notion of Substance” (1694), in The Philosophical Works of Leibniz, Translated from the original Latin and French, with notes of George Martin Duncan, New Haven, Tuttle, Morehouse & Taylor Publishers, 1890.

Leibniz, G.W. “The Monadology” (1714), in The Philosophical Works of Leibniz.

Lenoir, Timothy. The Strategy of Life: Teleology and Mechanics in Nineteenth-Century German Biology, Chicago and London, The University of Chicago Press, 1982.

Marx, Karl. Theses on Feuerbach, 1845.

Mayer, Arno J. Dynamics of counterrevolution in Europe, 1870-1956: an analytic framework, New York, Harper & Row, 1971.

Mayer, Arno J. The Persistance of the Old Regime: Europe to the Great War, New York, Pantheon Books, 1981.

Moll, J., R. de Oliveira-Souza, P.J. Eslinger, “Morals and the human brain: a working model”, Neuroreport, 2003, 14, 3, pp. 299-305.

Moll, J., R. de Oliveira-Souza, G.J. Garrido, I.E. Bramati, E.M. Caparelli-Daquer, M.L. Paiva, R. Zahn, J. Grafman, “The self as a moral agent: linking the neural bases of social agency and moral sensitivity”, Social Neuroscience, 2007; 2(3-4): 336-52. doi: 10.1080/17470910701392024.

Moll, J., J. Schulkin, “Social attachment and aversion in human moral cognition”, Neuroscience Biobehavioral Reviews, 2009 Mar; 33(3): 456-65. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2008.12.001. Epub 2008 Dec 14

Nowak, Magdalena. “The Complicated History of Einfühlung”, Argument, 1, 2, 2011, pp. 301-326.

Philonenko, Alexis. Métaphysique et politique chez Kant et Fichte, Paris, J. Vrin, 1997.

Rauer, Bernhard Sebastian Erne, Thomas Schweigler, Federica Cataldini, Mohammadamin Tajik, Jörg Schmiedmayer, “Recurrences in an isolated quantum many-body system”, Science, 20 Apr 2018, Vol. 360, Issue 6386, pp. 307-310, DOI: 10.1126/science.aan7938.

Safranski, Rüdiger. Schopenhauer und Die wilden Jahre der Philosophie (1987), Munchen/Wien, Carl Hanser Verlag, 2010. (See also Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy, Translated by Ewald Osers, Cambridge Ma., Harvard University Press, 1990; there is also a Romanian translation – Schopenhauer și anii sălbatici ai filozofiei – by Daniel Necșa, at Humanitas, București, 1998).

Eric Schliesser, Eric (Ed.), Sympathy: A History, Oxford Univ. Press, 2015.

Schmelz, Martin, Josep Call, Michael Tomasello. “Chimpanzees know that others make inferences”, PNAS, vol. 108 no. 7, 2010, pp. 3077–3079, doi: 10.1073/pnas.1000469108.

Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Idea (1818/enlarged in 1844), Seventh Edition, Translated by R.B. Haldane and J. Kemp, Volumes I, II, III, London, Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner & Co., 1909.

Schopenhauer, Arthur. The Basis of Morality (1841), Translated with Introduction and Notes by Arthur Brodrick Bullock, Cambridge, Trinity College, London, Swan Sonnenschein and Co, 1903

Schwartz, Michael A. Osborne P. Wiggins, “Psychosomatic medicine and the philosophy of life”, Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine, 5, 2, 2010, pp. 1-5.

Schweitzer, Albert. Civilization and Ethics (1923), Third edition, London, Adam & Charles Black, 1949.

Spinoza, Baruch. The Ethics, 1677, http://www.gutenberg.org/files/3800/3800-h/3800-h.htm#chap03

Stamenov, Maxim I. Vittorio Gallese (Eds.). Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and Language. Advances in Consciousness Research, Volume 42, Amsterdam / Philadelphia, John Benjamins Publishing Company, 2002.

Terrall, Mary. “Vis Viva Revisited”, History of Science, vol. 42, 2004, pp.189-209.

Vial, Fernand. The Unconscious in Philosophy, and French and European Literature: Nineteenth and Early Twentieth Century, Amsterdam and New York, Rodopi B.V., 2009.

Zadeh, L. A. “Quantitative Fuzzy Semantics”, Information Sciences, 3, 1971, pp. 159-176.

Downloads

Published

2019-12-30

How to Cite

BAZAC, A. . (2019). ARTHUR SCHOPENHAUER’S MIRROR: THE WILL, THE SUFFERING, THE COMPASSION AS PHILOSOPHICAL CHALLENGES. Studia Universitatis Babeș-Bolyai Philosophia, 64(3), 195 –. https://doi.org/10.24193/subbphil.2019.3.09

Issue

Section

Articles